|
On May 14, 1867, the 27-year-old Charles Sanders Peirce, who eventually founded Pragmatism, presented a paper entitled "On a New List of Categories" to the American Academy of Arts and Sciences. Among other things, this paper outlined a theory of predication involving three universal categories that Peirce continued to apply in philosophy and elsewhere for the rest of his life.〔Burch, Robert (2001, 2010), "(Charles Sanders Peirce )", ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy''. See §9 "Triadism and the Universal Categories".〕 In the categories one will discern, concentrated, the pattern which one finds formed by the three grades of clearness in "How to Make Our Ideas Clear" (1878 foundational paper for pragmatism), and in numerous other three-way distinctions in his work. ==The Categories== In Aristotle's logic, categories are adjuncts to reasoning that are designed to resolve equivocations, ambiguities that make expressions or signs recalcitrant to being ruled by logic. Categories help the reasoner to render signs ready for the application of logical laws. An equivocation is a variation in meaning — a manifold of sign senses — such that, as Aristotle put it about names in the opening of ''Categories'' (1.1a1–12), "Things are said to be named ‘equivocally’ when, though they have a common name, the definition corresponding with the name differs for each". So Peirce's claim that three categories are sufficient amounts to an assertion that all manifolds of meaning can be unified in just three steps. The following passage is critical to the understanding of Peirce's Categories:
The first thing to extract from this passage is the fact that Peirce's Categories, or "Predicaments", are predicates of predicates. Meaningful predicates have both ''extension'' and ''intension'', so predicates of predicates get their meanings from at least two sources of information, namely, the classes of relations and the qualities of qualities to which they refer. Considerations like these tend to generate hierarchies of subject matters, extending through what is traditionally called the ''logic of second intentions'',〔Such "intentions" are more like intensions than like aims or purposings.〕 or what is handled very roughly by ''second order logic'' in contemporary parlance, and continuing onward through higher intensions, or ''higher order logic'' and ''type theory''. Peirce arrived at his own system of three categories after a thoroughgoing study of his predecessors, with special reference to the categories of Aristotle, Kant, and Hegel. The names that he used for his own categories varied with context and occasion, but ranged from reasonably intuitive terms like ''quality'', ''reaction'', and ''representation'' to maximally abstract terms like ''firstness'', ''secondness'', and ''thirdness'', respectively. Taken in full generality, ''nth''-ness can be understood as referring to those properties that all ''n''-adic relations have in common. Peirce's distinctive claim is that a type hierarchy of three levels is generative of all that we need in logic. Part of the justification for Peirce's claim that three categories are both necessary and sufficient appears to arise from mathematical ideas about the reducibility of ''n''-adic relations. According to Peirce's Reduction Thesis,〔See "The Logic of Relatives," The ''Monist'', Vol. 7, 1897, pp. (161 )-217, see (p. 183 ) (via Google Books with registration apparently not required). Reprinted in the ''Collected Papers'', vol. 3, paragraphs 456-552, see paragraph 483.〕 (a) triads are necessary because genuinely triadic relations cannot be completely analyzed in terms or monadic and dyadic predicates, and (b) triads are sufficient because there are no genuinely tetradic or larger polyadic relations—all higher-arity ''n''-adic relations can be analyzed in terms of triadic and lower-arity relations. Others, notably Robert Burch (1991) and Joachim Hereth Correia and Reinhard Pöschel (2006), have offered proofs of the Reduction Thesis.〔 * Burch, Robert (1991), ''A Peircean Reduction Thesis: The Foundations of Topological Logic'', Texas Tech University Press, Lubbock, TX * Anellis, Irving (1993) "Review of ''A Peircean Reduction Thesis: The Foundations of Topological Logic'' by Robert Burch" in ''Modern Logic'' v. 3, n. 4, 401-406, Project Euclid Open Access (PDF 697 KB ). Criticism and some suggestions for improvements. * Anellis, Irving (1997), "Tarski's Development of Peirce's Logic of Relations" (''Google Book Search'' (Eprint )) in Houser, Nathan, Roberts, Don D., and Van Evra, James (eds., 1997), ''Studies in the Logic of Charles Sanders Peirce''. Anellis gives an account of a Reduction Thesis proof discussed and presented by Peirce in his letter to William James of August 1905 (L224, 40-76, printed in Peirce, C. S. and Eisele, Carolyn, ed. (1976), ''The New Elements of Mathematics by Charles S. Peirce'', v. 3, 809-835). * (Hereth Correia, Joachim ) and Pöschel, Reinhard (2006), "The Teridentity and Peircean Algebraic Logic" in ''Conceptual Structures: Inspiration and Application'' (ICCS 2006): 229-246, (Springer ). Frithjof Dau (calls it ) "the strong version" of proof of Peirce's Reduction Thesis. John F. Sowa in the same discussion (claimed ) that an explanation in terms of conceptual graphs is sufficiently convincing about the Reduction Thesis for those without the time to understand what Peirce was saying. * In 1954 W. V. O. Quine claimed to prove the reducibility of larger predicates to dyadic predicates, in Quine, W.V.O., "Reduction to a dyadic predicate", ''Selected Logic Papers''.〕 There have been proposals by Donald Mertz, Herbert Schneider, Carl Hausman, and Carl Vaught to augment Peirce's threefolds to fourfolds; and one by Douglas Greenlee to reduce them to twofolds.〔For references and discussion, see Burgess, Paul (circa 1988) "Why Triadic?: Challenges to the Structure of Peirce's Semiotic"; posted by Joseph M. Ransdell at ''(Arisbe )''.〕 Peirce introduces his Categories and their theory in ("On a New List of Categories" (1867) ), a work which is cast as a Kantian deduction and is short but dense and difficult to summarize. The following table is compiled from that and later works. (The context for interpretants is not psychology or sociology, but instead philosophical logic. In a sense, an interpretant is whatever can be understood as a conclusion of an inference. The context for the categories as categories is phenomenology, which Peirce also called phaneroscopy and categorics.) 抄文引用元・出典: フリー百科事典『 ウィキペディア(Wikipedia)』 ■ウィキペディアで「Categories (Peirce)」の詳細全文を読む スポンサード リンク
|